Photo de l'auteur
10+ oeuvres 4,236 utilisateurs 66 critiques 5 Favoris

A propos de l'auteur

Mark Reed Levin was born in Philadelphia, Pennsylvania on September 21, 1957. At the age of 19, he received a bachelor's degree in political science from Temple University. He is an attorney, author, conservative commentator, and the host of American syndicated radio show The Mark Levin Show. He afficher plus worked as an advisor to President Ronald Reagan's cabinet and was a chief of staff for Attorney General Edwin Meese. He is president of the Landmark Legal Foundation. He is the author of several books including Men in Black: How the Supreme Court Is Destroying America, Rescuing Sprite, Liberty and Tyranny, Ameritopia, and The Liberty Amendments. He received the Ronald Reagan Award from the American Conservative Union in 2001.Levin's New York Times bestsellers include Plunder and Deceit, and Rediscovering Americanism : And the Tyranny of Progressivism. (Bowker Author Biography) afficher moins
Crédit image: Mark Levin speaking at the 2018 Conservative Political Action Conference (CPAC) in National Harbor, Maryland. Please attribute to Gage Skidmore if used elsewhere. By Gage Skidmore from Peoria, AZ, United States of America - Mark Levin, CC BY-SA 2.0, https://commons.wikimedia.org/w/index.php?curid=66999758

Œuvres de Mark R. Levin

Oeuvres associées

George Washington: The Crossing (2013) — Préface — 120 exemplaires
Shattered Lives: 100 Victims of Government Health Care (2009) — Introduction — 3 exemplaires

Étiqueté

Partage des connaissances

Nom légal
Levin, Mark Reed
Date de naissance
1957-09-21
Sexe
male
Nationalité
USA
Lieu de naissance
Philadelphia, Pennsylvania, U.S.
Études
Temple University (BA, JD)
Professions
lawyer
radio show host
Relations
Levin, Jack E. (father)
Organisations
Citadel Media

Membres

Critiques

Writing: 5.0; Theme: 5.0; Content: 5.0; Language: 5.0; Overall: 5.0

Mr. Levin makes a great case that the title of his book is exactly correct- The Democrat Party Hates America. He shows how the current Democrat Party has been radicalized with very few among the leadership ranks of the party standing for traditional American principles and against the radical polices of the current administration. Highly recommend.

***February 28, 2024***
 
Signalé
jntjesussaves | Mar 2, 2024 |
I wanted to like this book, because it was a gift from my sister, and because it was about a rescue pup and the family who loved him. Despite all this, I found it dull and badly written. The language has been simplified to literally a 5th grade reading level, per Flesch Kincaid. Thus we are treated to such descriptive and emotional delights as:

"Her injury was fatal, and we were all devastated, especially my mother and grandfather."

"I looked at them with disgust and stormed out the door."

"She was very proud of her dad. The truth is that I did what every other dog lover would have done."

"I felt horrible for her. I whispered to the technician, 'She had to put the cat to sleep, didn't she?' She gave me a sad look and said they did."

"He was upset but very strong. I could see his eyes well up, but he held his emotions back."


The story itself is fairly mundane - the dogs do common doggie things and the author and his family experience the usual joys that our pets bring to our lives. I think the book can be useful to some for its description of the struggle most of us will have to face sooner or later: the end-of-life decisions we must make for a beloved pet who is suffering from an incurable illness or progressively poor health, and the guilt and spiritual questions that sometimes come with those decisions. It only amazes me that a middle aged man who has been a dog lover all his life had never before gone through it.

But even here, the clumsy prose and simplified language robs the story of emotional impact.

I'll keep this book on my shelves and treasure it, but only because it was a gift from my sister and for the thoughtful, loving inscription she wrote on the flyleaf, which moved me far more than anything else contained in it.
… (plus d'informations)
 
Signalé
Doodlebug34 | 18 autres critiques | Jan 1, 2024 |
1CThe Liberty Amendments 1D is first and foremost a highly thoughtful working through of proposed amendments to the United States Constitution by talk-show host and former government attorney Mark Levin. It is also an exploration of what has gone wrong in the development of federal power over the past two centuries and of a little-known remedy built into the Constitution itself. But more about that later.

Most of the book is devoted to ten amendments that Levin has written himself, but which would not likely be proposed or approved by a sitting Congress because these amendments tend to limit federal power and, in several cases, directly counter the authority of the Congress and other branches of the federal government by granting power to the state governments to check the federal government. These amendments are well thought out in that they do not give states cart blanch to go back and change laws written years before. So that while these measures allow the states, through their legislatures, to undo acts of Congress and even decisions of the Supreme Court (they also allow Congress to undo High Court decisions) these countermeasures would have to be launched within a specified number of months after the legislation or decision and would require super-majority votes of either two-thirds or three-fourths. Levin 19s amendments would not make it possible to exercise these checks of federal power frivolously, but if there were enough widespread opposition to any federal measure or decision, it could be neutered fairly quickly.

These amendments would rebalance the power exercised in U.S. civic life, taking supreme powers previously enjoyed by the branches of the federal government and putting them under the power of the states where they could be overruled whenever they prove to be sufficiently unpopular. In some cases, Levin 19s proposed amendments are a reaction to the undermining of intent of the original U.S. Constitution, which has crept toward ever more federal control over state sovereignty over the centuries and especially during the past century.

Where the intended purposes of government and relations between the state and federal governments have been changed over time in ways that Levin deems impossible to return to their original condition, he has opted to limit federal power in ways that only indirectly address the imbalance. For example, the power of the judiciary under the Constitution, which allowed it to review laws, has been used from early on to give the Supreme Court wider and wider powers of interpretation to the point where 1Cjudicial review 1D implies an almost unlimited authority to rewrite laws and expand and even radically alter the meanings of constitutional provisions to the point where their Framers would find them unrecognizable. Levin despairs that the philosophy behind such abuses is too entrenched to defeat it by reiterating the proper understanding of the Constitution 19s original intent or by reforming the curriculum of our law schools. He therefore attacks the problem by proposing term limits for the Court. This kind of indirect approach, evident in some of his proposals, reminds me of the song about the old lady who swallowed the spider to catch the fly. One problem is deemed insoluble by attacking it directly; so, instead, another measure will be introduced in order to counteract the problem. However, this is not said as a fatal criticism of his proposal, because he is probably right that this would be a more effective way of combating an error than would be a lengthy review of every past Court decision in order to overturn those that misinterpreted the letter of the law or misapplied precedents that were already contradictory to the law. Term limits would solve the problem with much less mess, even though, as Levin recognizes, it would work only if more judicious men and women were appointed to take the places of the retiring justices.

What is exciting about the best of these amendments is that they create specific legal steps by which the states, usually through their legislatures, can check and counter acts by the federal government. They provide exactly the measures that the Anti-Federalist delegates to the state ratifying conventions in 1788 rightly pointed out were missing from the Constitution, and which they asked for, but never got, from the original Constitution and its Federalist advocates: lawful measures that would allow states to stand up to the 1Cgeneral 1D or federal government. Even Hamilton and Madison, in the 1CFederalist Papers, 1D both appealed to armed insurrection as the most specifiable resort to which the states could turn under the Constitution, if they did not like what the federal government was doing to them!

The idea that set Levin to thinking about new amendments that might be proposed even though the Congress itself would never approve them, is that of the 1Cconvention of states, 1D which is mentioned in Article V of the U.S. Constitution as one of two ways that the document might be amended. It actually does what most of Levin 19s amendments do: allows the state legislatures to propose amendments to the U.S. Constitution whether Congress likes them or not. Throughout U.S. history, the only amendments that have been successfully added to the Constitution have been proposed by Congress and passed by a supermajority of both houses, then ratified by three-fourths of the states. There have been several times when the other method allowed by Article V, the Convention of the States, has been attempted but it has not come to pass. This process is described approvingly in 1CThe Federalist Papers 1D by both James Madison (Paper #43) and Alexander Hamilton (Paper #85). Advocates of this approach have included President Dwight D. Eisenhower and Senator Everett Dirksen, and Levin cites Professor Robert G. Natelson as a leading advocate whose published legal writings led Levin himself from skepticism to enthusiasm.

Levin deals with objections that the Convention of the States might become a runaway Constitutional Convention that would rewrite the Constitution entirely. This notion is quite a popular objection, but it requires a degree of paranoia bred of ignorance of the fact that the language of Article V makes the Convention of the States a process hemmed in by a narrow legal mandate to write amendments only and to submit them for ratification to the other states, requiring three fourths of them to vote for any new amendments just as is the case under the method where Congress submits new amendments to the states.

It is interesting to note that in one of his amendments, Levin suggests that the process of the Convention of the States itself be changed so that there would not need to be a national convention of the states. Under Levin 19s proposal, each state could meet separately and propose amendments. The only problem with this, for which Levin specifies a solution, is that each state, without the consultation of the other states, would be likely to come up with completely different and incompatible amendments; so Levin includes a provision that each amendment voted upon by all of the states must be worded exactly the same in order to become an amendment to the Constitution.

When I first heard Levin talk about his idea, I thought was brilliant. Having read his book now, I find that 1Cbrilliant 1D is not strong enough a word. It seems to me that Levin 19s proposed amendments are what James Madison might have come up with had he had the benefit of looking back on two and a quarter centuries of American constitutional history. If not Madison, then certainly Thomas Jefferson would have approved.
… (plus d'informations)
 
Signalé
MilesFowler | 3 autres critiques | Jul 16, 2023 |
IN 1CAmeritopia 1D Mark Levin 19s premise is that the political left is hopelessly utopian and therefore fanciful, not to say fanatical, in its hopes for change, while the right is realistic in its estimation of the human need for freedom within the bounds of a limited government that protects individual liberty. He boils down Plato 19s 1CRepublic, 1D Thomas More 19s 1CUtopia, 1D Thomas Hobbes 19 1CLeviathan, 1D John Locke 19s 1CSecond Treatise on Civil Government, 1D Charles de Montesquieu 19s 1CThe Spirit of the Laws, 1D what Jefferson, Madison and other Founders of the United States made of the previously listed writings and how they were influenced by them in writing the Declaration of Independence and the U.S. Constitution. He also describes Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels 19 1CThe Communist Manifesto. 1D Levin next examines how America 19s Constitutional experiment looked half a century after the founding when Alexis de Tocqueville visited the United States and then reported on what he found in 1CDemocracy in America. 1D Levin follows up by examining how the governance of the United States came to be as it is today, and how it is different from what the Founders intended and what Tocqueville saw 180 years ago, focusing on the role of presidents Woodrow Wilson and Franklin Roosevelt who enacted their visions of federal government growth as an 1Cimprovement 1D on the original Constitution in the early twentieth century, thereby departing from the original intent of the Founding generation. Wilson certainly promoted and defined 14if he did not invent 14the term 1Cliving Constitution, 1D whereby the document is not seen as fixed law but as an open-ended guide that can and should be interpreted and reinterpreted according to an era 19s 1Cbest thought 1D (read 1Celite thought 1D).

Levin 19s book is a masterful polemic, educating as it seeks to influence. Whether you agree or disagree with Levin 19s conclusions, you will be engaged intellectually by the ideas he presents as well as his commentary on them. Utopianism from Plato to Hobbes to Marx has offered humanity a hope-filled fantasy that not only cannot fulfill its promise but must descend into a tyranny. All of the utopias outlined in this book deny human nature, put power in the hands of a few even while pretending that all men have 14or would if they knew what was good for them 14freely chosen to put their faith in a king, dictator or oligarchy; they all urge radical equality, which never raises men up but rather brings them all down.

To put Levin 19s conclusion in my own words, the bloody Pol Pot regime of Cambodia in the 1970s should be seen as adhering more faithfully to utopian radical egalitarianism than any other in history because Pol Pot dehumanized everyone equally and, if they resisted being dehumanized, he killed them equally. This is what Levin would call a hard or 1Creal 1D tyranny. The path to such a tyranny can either be a precipitous revolution or, in the case of the United States, a soft tyranny under which the individual human spirit and its most compatible institutions of free trade and representative government are gradually hectored out of existence by myriad petty regulations and a striving for procrustean egalitarianism.

Reading this book is not especially easy, though I thought all the while I was reading it how easy Levin has made the reader 19s task by selecting, assembling and summarizing quotations from so many classics. If anything, he has made a great deal of it easier to absorb than it would otherwise be if, say I for example, were to spend the next year or two intensely trying to read all of these works for myself.

Levin 19s writing does become repetitive since many passages from writers such as Locke and Montesquieu are not only quoted in the chapters devoted to each of them but are repeated in subsequent chapters. This and his tendency to summarize the quotations is helpful, especially considering that, while all of these thinkers are challenging, Plato and Montesquieu, being translated from foreign languages, are at least presented in more or less modern English, while More, Hobbes and Locke are quoted in their original language(s), which represent stages of the development of English from pre-Elizabethan to post-Elizabethan to pre-American Revolution. Consequently, More 19s English is relatively difficult to understand while Locke 19s is comparatively easier but still quaint to the modern eye and ear, and the difficulty of reading Hobbes 19 English falls in between those two.

Is Levin 19s premise a conceit that exaggerates? Are all leftists utopians? Are there no utopians on the right? I believe that, in general, Levin is right, that utopianism too often rejects human nature, trying to remold people into 1Cideal beings 1D subservient to a greater good that too often turns out to be the whims of an elite leadership within the utopian model. This is true of Plato, More and Hobbes in their openly utopian models, but it also turns out to be the reality of every socialist experiment even when the advocates deny that their socialism is utopian or that their leaders are a permanent feature of their scheme. Rather, every form of socialism seems to devolve immediately into nothing more than a system of neo-feudalism where a few privileged leaders lord it over masses of deliberately impoverished peasants.

Ironically, Levin notes that some opponents of the U.S. Constitution have implied or stated that constitutionalism is utopian, the exact opposite of Levin 19s thesis. To them, their fantasies are factual while a system designed to accommodate rather than change the facts of human nature, such as Madison 19s conception of the Constitution, is utopian. (This reminds me of the most profound insight into the mind of Adolf Hitler that I have read: Toward the end of World War II, as unmistakable evidence of impending defeat poured in every day, Hitler turned to an aid and expressed frustration over the lack of connection between the data coming to him from the world and the reality that he knew to be the true state of things.)

It is not generally through an embrace of constitutionalism that the right itself takes up anything like utopianism, but there are questions of utopianism on the conservative and classical liberal side that bear consideration. For example, James Madison, the Father of the Constitution, constructed a clever system of separation of competing powers at the federal level that seems to have worked but only for a few decades. Was he too clever by half? Should he have followed the advice of the Anti-federalists and put far more emphasis on the separation of powers between state and federal? Perhaps, although the Federalists saw as their mandate the arrangement of a national government; explicitly tinkering with the power of the states, even to define powers in their favor, might have backfired and not helped to get the states to accept the Constitution. Such considerations have more to do with the politics of the day and little to do with utopianism.

Where conservatives *might* be guilty of utopianism 14especially the sin of denying human nature 14is in regard to questions of lawfully enforced morality. Take for example the trade in illicit drugs. Conservatives want to maintain laws against traffic and use of certain drugs even though this is social engineering without regard to human nature in all of its aspects: not only the tendency of some people to use drugs but the economic motive to supply a demand; paradoxically, laws against drugs motivate and empower career criminals to traffic in drugs. Kill or send any of them to prison and you do not deter but rather encourage the remaining traffickers to step up their activities and effectively call up new dealers to take the places of those removed. Drug dealers will only thank the police for eliminating their competitors for them. Yet for many conservatives this marketplace logic matters not at all because drugs are immoral and therefore should be illegal; facts cannot be allowed to get in the way of that reality. Conservatives do not even notice what ought to their first clue that something is amiss in their drug-warrior convictions: regardless of their campaign rhetoric, most leftist utopians have been drug-warriors themselves. The conservative might think that this is only because the left can 19t bring itself to legalize drugs because of the public backlash that might result, but actually drug prohibition is a pretty good way to control people. If rank and file leftists do tend to use illegal substances, this only makes them that much more vulnerable to the utopian masterminds to control them.

Perhaps the reason why I have myself have journeyed from libertarianism to a more conservative libertarianism in recent years has something to do with the utopianism of some of my fellow libertarians. They seem to think that libertarianism should lead to kicking over the traces and achieving a quasi-anarchistic (or not so quasi-) society, a world where each individual is free to radically reject the social contracts made by past generations. This is a species of ignorance of human nature possibly akin to that of the leftist utopians, albeit one that trusts the individual rather than being like the traditional utopias from Plato to Marx and beyond, which all distrust the individual in the masses while peculiarly trusting the individual who has been sactioned to run the government. Yet some libertarians distrust all the precedents of social relations, including the Constitution in the American setting; they reject all the laws that promote social relations in the present generation because they personally never voted for them. It is because of tradition, though, that we know and trust that others will keep their word and fulfill their contracts with us. As Jefferson said in the Declaration of Independence, breaking with traditional ways of doing things such as governance should not be done lightly but only for good cause.

Ultimately, the correctness of Levin 19s thesis is due to the overall difference between the left 19s insistence that we must change human nature to conform with the utopian ideal, on the one hand, and the tendency on the other of classical liberalism 14a considerable though not the only component of modern American conservatism 14to observe human nature and celebrate its strengths while only providing enough government to curb its weaknesses. As I hinted above, Madison 19s idea was to use the weaknesses of human nature against each other by creating a society that is too free and various for factions bent on evil ends to achieve unity and thereby majority. This idea seems to have worked for the first fifty years of the Republic, to judge from Tocqueville 19s account, but subsequently there has been an erosion of the safeguards that the Framers of the Constitution tried to build into their system. The balance of power between the states and the federal government, taken for granted by the Framers as not needing too much special protection, has shifted as the few places in the Constitution where the states 19 powers are mentioned have been changed or ignored. Today, federal office holders whether executive, legislative or judicial, tend to assume that the federal government should interfere with the operation of state and local government and, because some of them expect to transfer between branches of the branches of the federal government in the course of their careers, they are more jealous keepers of the entire federal government 19s power and less so of that of the branch that they temporarily occupy.

In addition, as Levin points out, the federal government has expanded the power of the legislative and executive by creating many new bureaucracies that produce so many new rules and regulations that Levin says that no one can count them. What is more, a great many of these rules are redundant as they are made by departments and bureaus whose jurisdictions overlap. But the most worrisome feature of this governmental growth is that elected representatives have abdicated their authority to unelected and too often unvetted and unconfirmed officials who run the government entities that increasingly regulate our lives. Elections are virtually irrelevant so long as these bureaucracies exercise so much of their power without oversight by elected officials; and often the lack of oversight is due the degree of complexity caused by Congress and the executive having created so much bureaucracy that they are incapable of understanding themselves let alone overseeing. (In this regard, it is interesting that President Franklin Roosevelt, having created a vast number of bureaucracies, eventually made an attempt to bring back under his own control some of the power he had earlier ceded to them.)

The arrogant conceit of the 1Cmasterminds 1D is that their idealistic theories can be made to work by shear will regardless of real-world difficulties, Particularly in the fields of energy and fuel standards, the government seems to think that it can command technological advances by fiat at the same time that its regulations suppress innovation.

Levin rehearses the history of social insurance from Social Security to Medicare and Medicaid to the latest and largest expansion of government entitlements, the Patient Protection and Affordability Care Act (PPACA) colloquially known as Obamacare. Both its official and vernacular names are ironic since the new law will certainly protect patients from nothing and render decent health care unaffordable, and President Obama had nothing to do with writing it and, I wager, still has never read it. Not only will the massive law cause costs to skyrocket, private insurance companies to go out of business and employers to end health benefits since the federal government will take over their provision, but an unknowable number of agencies will necessarily be created to deal with the administration of the new law, and each of them will have to have its own budget that will increase every year and never decrease.

What Levin means to present is a choice for the future of his country: America as it was founded, based on individualism, private property, industry and virtue, or 1CAmeritopia 1D where utopianism 1Cmetastasizes 1D into the opposite from the kind of society that made the United States successful and the destination of choice for everyone in the world who had an ambition and a desire to make a better life for themselves and their families. (Utopians often aim to undermine or abolish the family, BTW.) In the classical liberal view 14and according to the evidence of upward mobility in societies that take the classical liberal approach even in part 14it is the pursuit of self-interest that paradoxically improves the lives of everyone in the community and the nation, not the pursuit of equal redistribution of wealth and outcomes as recommended by the classical utopians and modern expertocracies of the progressive liberals and their socialist cousins. No government can redistributes wealth; it will rather only redistribute poverty.

Levin admits that he does not have a crystal ball. A dystopic utopia (a redundancy) is not necessarily our destiny; however, Ameritopia 14America turned into a tyrannical utopia 14is path we are already on; it is always easiest to stay on the same road rather than discover where it was that we took the wrong turn so as to get back on the right road. Our current destination, Ameritopia, might seem like the promise of a better tomorrow, but whether achieved by revolution or evolution utopia always rather seems to become the tyranny today.
… (plus d'informations)
 
Signalé
MilesFowler | 4 autres critiques | Jul 16, 2023 |

Listes

Prix et récompenses

Vous aimerez peut-être aussi

Auteurs associés

Statistiques

Œuvres
10
Aussi par
2
Membres
4,236
Popularité
#5,936
Évaluation
4.0
Critiques
66
ISBN
81
Langues
3
Favoris
5

Tableaux et graphiques